This will be a continuously growing list as long as this blog remains up and I continue to find insights about life. To me, poetry is compact philosophy, and proverbs are compact poetry. I hope you, the reader, can find some wisdom here. (As far as I am aware, most or all of these are original, though there are likely similar phrases throughout the internet. Wisdom doesn't change.)
- Never justify your existence through someone else. Live for others, but do not make others your reason to live.
- Apologize once if they demand you to; apologize once and make it up to them double if they forgive you first; if they make you apologize more than once, they do not deserve any apologies.
- If there is no right way to do something, then there is no wrong way either.
- Assuming you are always right is the shortest path to being wrong.
- People who claim to know what life is about are probably the most unsure.
- "They" and "us" are the most divisive words in the English language.
- Apathy is contagious.
- Just because you do not like something does not mean someone else should be prohibited from it.
- Being comfortable in silence is being comfortable with yourself.
- Changing yourself starts and ends with you. Others may affect you, but only you can change who you are.
- You are over something only when you stop using it as an excuse.
- Anyone who said there is no such thing as a stupid question has never worked customer service.
- If all things are worthless, then all things are equally worth doing. True nihilism is optimism.
Philosophy for the modern person. Concise, understandable, relatively accurate, and littered with dark humor. Suggestions? Questions? Want to go on a date? Email crashcoursephilosophy@gmail.com, or be a normal person and leave a comment on the Facebook page.
Thursday, May 29, 2014
Sunday, May 18, 2014
A Case For Innate Ideas
This is my thesis from college. It isn't terribly boring, I swear. It is also probably the smartest thing I've written in my life.
A Case For Innate Ideas
Introduction
This is less of a paper and more of a conversation. As
opposed to the popular in-depth point-by-point analytic style we will be
discussing broad ideas to generate thought and discussion. In this conversation
I will present empiricism as outlined by John Locke as it seems to be the most
concise and complete version to contend with the case of innate ideas. I will
give an account of consciousness, ideas, human understanding of ideas, and the
abilities of our faculties being distinguished from innate ideas. Empiricism is
a useful and correct account for gaining knowledge, however, it does not
account for certain ideas which I argue to be innate. It is beyond a reasonable
doubt that innate ideas exist.
Empiricism from Locke to Kant
The base claim of empiricism is that all knowledge comes
from experience[1]. Empiricism rose as a
response to popular rationalist ideas. Rationalism, and later skepticism,
distrusted knowledge gained by the senses as it is not necessarily reliable.
Take Descartes' evil demon argument, or Hume's classic sensory experiment with
the bowls of water at different temperatures. Non-Humean empiricists argued
against cases such as these on the grounds that if we cannot trust our senses
then we are unable to actually know
anything about the world, essentially being stuck at the end of Descartes' first meditations. There is a
false dichotomy here where one must either take empiricism to its logical end
and become a skeptic, or to accept rationalism and limit knowledge exclusively
to one's own self, unable to make any knowledge claim gained by the senses. I
reject both of these, taking a page out of Roderick Chisholm's Problem of the Criterion";
"What few philosophers
have had the courage to recognize is this: we can deal with the problem only by
begging the question. It seems to me that if we do recognize this fact, as we
should, then it is unseemly for us to try to pretend that it isn’t so. One may object: 'Doesn’t this mean, then,
that the skeptic is right after all?' I would answer: 'Not at all. His view is
only one of the three possibilities and in itself has no more to recommend it
than the others do. And in favor of our approach there is the fact that we do
know many things, after all.'”[2]
Locke separated experience into two categories. "Outer
experience comes through the senses and provides sensory qualities, e.g.,
color, heat, hardness, sweetness, etc. Inner experience comes through reflection
[of sense experiences] and provides ideas of non-tangible and non-sensory
things such as beliefs, ideas, thoughts, doubts, etc."[3]
The tricky word to get around here is experience. The cogito, I think, therefore I am, presupposes the
experience of existing, or experiences that require a being to exist in the
first place. Mathematics requires the experience of either self-awareness,
which would lead through reflection to the idea of other things to eventually
develop basic algebra, or the experience of basic numerical knowledge. Kant
used the example of 7+5=12, needing only the 7+5 to rationally conclude the
existence of 12, but that is not so. The subject must have knowledge of what 7
is, what addition is, and what 5 is, as well as how these interact. I concede
the possibility to rationalize mathematics after the base rules are understood,
but those base rules are gained through experiencing space and time, not merely
through reason. A priori knowledge
does not have any feasible place in this epistemological account. "Locke
claimed that knowledge is direct awareness of facts concerning the agreement or
disagreement among our ideas. By 'ideas,' he meant mental objects, and by
assuming that some of these mental objects represent non-mental objects he
inferred that this is why we can have knowledge of a world external to our
minds."[4]
I certainly am not at the level of Immanuel Kant,
although he pursued the same line we are walking right now between empiricism
and rationalism. Kant was dissatisfied with the claims from both empiricists
and rationalists. "...Empiricist positions are untenable because they
necessarily presuppose the very claims they set out to disprove."[5]
Kant primarily refuted Hume by proving that synthetic a priori assertions existed, that of time and space, although I
disagree on the grounds that a subject must necessarily experience time and
space in order to reason it. "A
synthetic a priori claim constructs upon and adds to what is contained analytically
in a concept without appealing to experience." [6]
Kant followed this to its logical end and found that we cannot know anything
about ultimate reality other than its existence. This is because we see the
observable world, that of our senses, whereas ultimate reality is unfiltered,
an experience we can never come to realize in any aspect. "We humans must
therefore despair of ever knowing of God, justice, immortality, or freedom,
since all of these ideas overreach the human capability for knowledge."[7]
All of these things are unknowable by sense experience, as ideas and
consciousness suffer from the same obscurity, and are unable to be known by
humans. I agree with Kant in this respect. My argument of innate ideas tries to
synthesize empiricism and rationalism in a different manner than Kant did, although
the end of Kant's work seems to be the end of any major epistemological work
done on empiricism.
Consciousness and Ideas
Now
that we have a framework for the current state of empiricism, we may ask the
question, "What is an idea?" The broadest definition possible appears
to be "any conception existing in the mind as a result of mental
understanding, awareness, or activity", or "any content of the
mind."[8] Virtually every faction of
epistemology would agree on this definition. As Locke famously stated for the
empiricist viewpoint, "Let us then
suppose the mind to be... white paper, void of all characters, without any
ideas; how comes it to be furnished? .... To this I answer in one word, from
experience."[9]
From this we can derive an important distinction; there are ideas and there are
faculties to acquire those ideas. Locke goes into detail about simple ideas,
such as roundness, shininess, firmness, etc., and complex ideas, the conjoining
of simple ideas to create the idea of objects such as coins. We will not be
covering that though since it is not highly relevant to innate ideas. We have
established our concept of ideas from empiricism as thoughts or impressions
gained from sense experience and reflection.
Now we must discuss
consciousness. Unfortunately, we are only able to determine the consciousness
of ourselves. As the great debates over strong AI have shown us, as well as
Kant's conclusion about the noumenal world, the knowledge of consciousness of
others is unknowable, or at the very least inaccessible by modern standards.
This may change at some point in the future but for now we must work on these
grounds. Although we are unable to deductively infer the consciousness of
another being, we do have the ability to inductively infer beyond reasonable
doubt whether something is conscious. For instance, if we come across a tree
with initials inscribed into it, we infer that an intelligent being was the
cause. In the same way we can look at other beings and determine if they are
conscious of their surroundings. Other humans are assumed to have consciousness
whereas rocks are presumed to not have consciousness.
Continuing this stream,
we can see the results of a conscious being in its work; a human will toil,
grow crops or livestock, gather materials, and commit other actions as a result
of its consciousness. Rocks may fall due to gravity or other forces but we do
not see rocks committing actions of their own will. We establish the
consciousness of a being based on its actions, but we are never truly aware of
the conscious beings motivations or ideas. The being can give an explanation,
such as hunger or pleasure, but that requires communication. The subject could
be lying or have their senses impaired or have an ulterior motive or simply not
speak in the same terms as the listener. We have no way to directly determine
any other beings ideas beyond a reasonable doubt, and to this end we are also
unable to determine the content of that consciousness. This, of course,
involves that beings thoughts. Therefore we have established the first point
of my argument; one can only be directly and assuredly aware of one's own
thoughts and contents.
There is the apparent
problem of solipsism that must be dealt with. To defeat it on these grounds we
do not need to prove that every human is another conscious being. We need only
to prove that there exists one other true being, to which I turn to Max
Scheler, an empiricist who strongly supports the idea of the tabula rasa. In his essay "The Being of the Person," Scheler
makes a convincing case for the existence of God as well as the nature of the
person in general. His defense of God is my defense against solipsism.
Scheler makes the
assertion that every "world [is] the correlate of the person. Hence there
is an individual world responding to every individual person. "[10] Clearly this is a
solipsistic notion when a person believes themselves to be the only person.
However, he makes the distinction that a person "lives into the
world" but the world they live in is the world of the person which
contains an "abstract objectivity" of others worlds.
"The
world is by no means in idea. It is an absolute, always concrete, individual
being... The fact that truth about the world and the absolute world is, in a
certain sense, a 'personal truth' is due not to any supposed 'relativity' or
'subjectivity'... but to the essential interconnection between the person and
the world... All [personal worlds] are... parts of the macrocosm - if there is
one concrete world into which all persons look. And the personal correlate of
the macrocosm would be the idea of an infinite and perfect person of spirit,
one whose acts would be given to us in their essential determinations in
act-phenomenology, which pertains to the acts of all possible persons. But this
'person' would have to be concrete simply to fulfill the essential conditions
of a reality. Thus the idea of God is cogiven with the unity and identity and
singularity of the world on the basis of an essential interconnection of
complexes. Therefore, if we posit one concrete world as real, it would be
absurd not to posit the idea of a concrete spirit."[11]
From this defense we must conclude that there is a God and through our
perception of God we may understand there to be other people. Additionally, we
must also realize that there is an absolute world with knowledge to be gained
through the senses. It may be possible to reject a physical reality and a
notion of God as the connector of all realities, but that would mean the
solipsist is the only perceiver in all of the universe. There is a plethora of
problems that the solipsist must overcome in order to stay a solipsist. Instead
of devoting anymore of this paper to refuting them, I will move on with the
argument. There are too many ad hocs
to deal with, and solipsism is not the main focus of this paper anyways.
Actions and Ideas
We have established that
we are only able to access our own thoughts, ideas, and consciousness. This
does not mean they are completely out of reach, but that we are unable to give an
answer with full assurance, although we do this every day without thinking
about it. How? If someone steals, we assume them to be thinking selfishly. If someone
places a bet, we assume they are thinking their bet will win. If someone wears
a certain outfit, we assume them to have thought about that before choosing it.
Why do we assume these things people think? Actions are the only access we have
to other thoughts. What someone does, how someone speaks, the choice of words,
the timing of their actions; all of these play a role in our understanding of
their thought processes. The entirety of the strong AI argument is based on the
problem that persists in this respect.
How do we correlate the
actions of a being with its thoughts? We understand a being to be conscious if
it moves around of its own will and performs actions to ensure its survival. A
rock is clearly not conscious, although it will move because of forces acting
upon it such as gravity. What differentiates a human from a rock is that its actions
are attributed to its thoughts instead of gravity or other forces. There are
obvious problems here concerning creatures of abstract thought and complex
ideas. For instance, someone may commit an action of theft and, given our only
knowledge of the event is the theft and our assumptions from previous thefts,
we may assume them to be selfish. However, with more information we can
understand them to be needy, requiring medicine for their sick parent.
Yet another problem
arises when trying to understand another creatures thought's based on their
actions; knowledge in this sense is completely dependent upon each participant's
level of experience. Jumping back a bit, empiricism states that all knowledge
is founded in experience. Had I never been the victim of theft before or known
a victim of theft, I would not understand what theft is or the reasons behind
it. I would likely assume the perpetrator to have mistaken something as their
own or for it to have been an accident. It is simply because I do not have
enough ideas, I do not have enough experience, that the truth of another's
ideas or intentions may remain unknown to me. The same argument may be made for
animals or machines having ideas. It is merely a matter of humans not having
enough information or experience that we are unable to recognize the contents
of their minds, but, again, this is not the place for that debate.
Here is my second point;
one is only capable of determining another being's thoughts beyond a
reasonable doubt based on that beings actions. This should not be a very
disagreeable point to the empiricist. If Joe has never had the experience of
the color green then he cannot be expected to draw a proper rainbow. If Ted has
never taken a class on quantum physics no one would be disappointed that he
cannot explain Schrödinger's cat adequately. Without needing to go into much
detail, this second point compliments the empirical mindset rather nicely. We will
now look at an example which reverses that, and then reflect that onto babies.
My reasoning for this is simple; by the time humans understand how to
communicate their ideas and to formulate extremely abstract ideas, they've had
so many new ideas brought into their minds that it is nearly impossible for
them to determine if one of them was innate or not without extreme inquiry.
Furthermore, we must distinguish between survival mechanics and the notion of
innate ideas, which I will argue are one-in-the-same. Finally, I will
distinguish between the motivational ideas which all other ideas are rooted in
and practical ideas, of which there are very few discernible examples.
The Bird
There is a bird in
Australia known as the incubator bird, which will be shortened to IB. The male
IB creates a large mound to attract a female. This mound is very large, about
the size of a small bus. The female lays her eggs which are placed inside the
mound. The male tends to the eggs, ensuring the temperature and humidity are at
the right levels for the eggs to incubate properly. Each mound only lasts for
one season, so when all of the chicks hatch the mound is deserted. The chicks
are not helped by either parent but are left to survive on their own.
The chick itself is
where I will start. It is born into darkness, underground, away from any
possible communication with its parents. The chick hatches, gets on its back,
and starts digging up. This process takes several hours, even days. The chick
then gets to the top and walks away, ready to survive and do the exact same
thing as its parents with absolutely no sense data or communication data on
what to do, yet it will still do it. How can empiricism or any sort of
experience-based theory of knowledge explain these actions? How does it know to
dig, or even in which direction to dig? How does it know what to eat or how to
perform the mating ritual? This species does not travel in packs, so societal
information is not an option. There is virtually no way we can describe the
chick's ideas based on its actions other than the ideas being innate.
To make a short tangent,
from the evolutionary standpoint humans share the same ancestor as these birds.
It is not a wild theory to say that these birds have ideas since many of the
same biological components can be found in both species. Although many people
may not believe birds to have consciousness it is at least plausible for them
to have ideas, that is to say cognitive functions with a directed goal or sense
of intentionality.
For humans I use the
example of infants knowing to suckle. There is no doubt that infants have not
breastfed prior to leaving the womb. In fact, they have never ingested anything
through their mouths up to this point. Yet when the baby is born it knows that
its mother can provide it with nutrients. There is absolutely no experience of
this event prior to its happening, virtually no cognitive abilities worth
mentioning, no form of long-term memory to speak of. How does the infant know
to suckle? There is no way to attribute this to experience. Therefore, this is
a possible case of an innate practical idea that exists in humans.
Programs, Instincts, and Ideas
It may be argued that
the bird is acting in these ways due to its survival instincts. It was born to
react in such a way when presented with a certain situation. When it sees a
worm, its first reaction is to eat it; when a certain time of the year is
perceived, it decides to build a mound; when an egg is laid into the mound, it
acts a certain way towards the egg. It does all of these things because of its
survival instincts to do so, it's ideas to do so. The same case can go for the
infant as well. There is a much more important question I pose to the
empiricist though; what differentiates practical innate ideas from survival
instincts? Certainly there are things gained from sense data and experience;
fire is hot, the sun sets and rises, rain falls on occasion. These are undisputedly
gained from experience. These are examples of practical ideas, ideas that are
relevant to how a being can manipulate its environment to achieve a goal.
The very essence of an
innate idea is steeped in an unfortunate foundation; they have no discernible
origin. To say an idea was inspired by such and such experience is to attribute
it to something learned, something experienced. As explained earlier, it is
possible for a single perceiver to use reflection of its very existence to gain
ideas of things it never experienced through the senses but that exist in
theory. There is a severe difference between theory and action in this regard though.
The IB knows to dig a certain
direction, knows what to eat and how
to catch it, and knows to build a
mound the next season purely because it must know these things to survive, not
because of its own experiences. This can be seen in other animals too, yet
is attributed to instinct.
Why aren't instincts considered
innate practical ideas? Animals act in certain ways across an entire species.
Virtually all dogs will chase a laser pointer. Virtually all cats will attack
an object moving quickly in front of them. Virtually all bears are deathly
protective of their young. The instinct to suckle is surely an idea that the
infant has or it would have no motivation to do so. It is mere bigotry to say
there animals do not have ideas based on their actions. Consciousness may be
another issue, but instinct and practical innate ideas are synonymous. Neither
originates from experience, yet permeates a creatures actions. We must remember
that humans are animals too. Humans are mammals with the potential for powerful
cognitive abilities, but all of modern science points to those abilities lying
dormant until a certain age.
The Two Proposed Innate Ideas, A
Distinction Between Practical and Motivational
There are at least two
undeniable motivations present in all humans, regardless of location, society,
class, race, etc.; all humans are driven to pleasure and/or power. These two
have been used interchangeably over the centuries and tend to directly impact
each other. There are virtually no ideas in all of human culture that surface
as much as these two, or any ideas that do not have some relation to them. They
are so strong that many religions consider them a natural sin, a by-product of
man's fall from grace. If there is such a thing as an innate idea in humans, it
is one or both of these. This portion of the essay will focus on their use in
society. I would like to note that these ideas likely dominate animals
motivations as well, but for the sake of this discussion we will primarily be
looking at humans. It is equally important to note that power and pleasure are
motivational innate ideas as opposed to practical innate ideas. They are the
root of why we do things but have no influence on the attainment of them.
Almost
every society will address at least one of the two proposed motivational innate
ideas, although it is more often both. Society usually exemplifies those with
strong desires for power or discoveries that increase the pleasure of the
society at large. Take the examples of rock stars or professional athletes; those
with power are perceived as greater sexual partners and as more persuasive.
Choosing one sexual partner over another may be attributable to societal
interactions and self-perseverance, but this still has the underlying
frameworks of pleasure and power as motivations for actions. The main backing
for virtually all people even competing to become successful are these same
motivations. They wish to find a better mate, to use their success to change
the world around them, or they do it purely for their own enjoyment.
The counter-point may be
made that pleasure is derived from power, which does not counter my argument at
all. Why does a creature seek pleasure if it is not something innately desired
to be obtained? Creatures seek the best conditions to produce offspring, which
often involves power. There is the religious argument that pleasure is derived
from submitting to a higher authority, such as God, which results in vows of
celibacy or giving up power to God's will. However, this is still a form of
pleasure for the submitting person. Both may not be gained in unison, but one
can never be discussed without either implying or addressing the other two.
To further this concept,
there are never laws or rules promoting or helping people to gain pleasure or
power without giving pleasure or power to another person. On the contrary, the
rules and laws of religion and society are specifically designed to stave off
these desires for the greater good of the community. Sexually abused children
or tyrannical states are generally considered a bad thing by and for the
majority populous. Societies understand this concept to be true of most people,
as do many classic psychologists and scientists. Most empirical studies are
framed in such a way that the human is merely an animal that thinks. Pavlov's
dogs were conditioned in the same way as people riding the train to work every
day. However, as much as society tries to quell these motivations within its
own people, the society as a whole seeks these same things over other
societies. Most nations today base their health on their economy in relation to
other economies, i.e. the issue of power. Some nations are proud of their
sexual freedom while others base the overall happiness, i.e. pleasure of the
people, with how successful the country is doing.
There is no empirical
grounding for the immediate desire of power or pleasure among humans, or for
the certain instincts animals have. It could be argued that the suckling infant
has both ideas as motivating its suckling. Toddlers always seek to prove
themselves to their parents, the givers of power. Why do they do this? They
seek pleasure or power from their main example of what pleasure and power are.
They are hard-wired to do it, and since there is no experience necessary to
understand this desire, it is itself outside of the boundaries of empiricism.
Experience is required to understand how
to gain them but not for the desire to have them in the first place. It may be
the case that the child wishes to get away from its parents. This still
supports the three principles as the child seeks pleasure, to be away from the
parents, and power, to show the parents that it is not under their control.
This brings us to the final point to solidify the case for innate ideas; motivational
innate ideas exist nearly universally within every living being which have no
founding in experience, desires which drive every action those beings take.
Within the empiricist worldview these can be understood only as innate ideas,
existing within the being prior to experience.
*It is important to
distinguish between an instinct and a sense. Whereas the desire to have sex is
an instinct, sight and hearing are senses. The senses are used to gain data
from the perceived world. The senses are fallible and link the person to the
world around them. Senses are used to experience and manipulate. Senses are not
disputed to be the primary way beings come to understand the world around them.
Instincts are much more enigmatic. They have no basing in any sense data but
are a driving force behind a creatures actions. It is possible to doubt that a
sense is giving the correct information since the sense is merely gaining
information. Instincts are action-based whereas senses are information
gathering. It is possible to doubt either one while being sure about other, or
to doubt or be sure of both. There is a clear and distinct separation between
the two.
As a final distinction
for this section, there are the motivational innate ideas of power and pleasure
which we have already discussed and the practical innate ideas. These practical
ideas are unfathomably difficult to pinpoint in any being, as they are much
more easily attributable to experience within a short time after birth. We
return to the suckling infant and the IB.
The suckling is
assuredly a practical innate idea. It is practical because it involves a
manipulation of the world to fulfill a desire or motivational innate idea. The
infant is aware that it must feed to survive, which may be attributable to it's
sense of hunger. However, experience fails in that the infant knows how to feed, and had it not known how it
would not survive. The issue of consciousness aside, the infant requires having
some sort of idea to commit to the action of suckling. Modern science tells
that long-term memory is not created until a few months to a few years after
birth, demolishing any attempt to ground the suckling in experience. Each time
the infant suckles for the first few months is like a new experience.
Regardless of this shattering fact, had the infant not had some knowledge to
suckle throughout human history it would surely have died before finding other
sources of edible food. Another related issue is the knowledge of the mother to
allow the infant to breast feed. How does the mother know to have an infant
breast feed unless she had done it too, or seen another do it? This strand of
thought boils down to a "chicken or the egg" argument. The only
acceptable answer is that suckling is a practical innate idea with no
attribution to sensory experience.
The IB has the same problem
as the infant to the empiricists. Digging it's way out of the mound is related
to it's survival. There is no sensory experience telling the IB that there is
anything above the mound, or even that there is anything other than darkness.
In order to survive the IB must be aware of the world outside the mound. It
must have the practical idea to dig up in order to survive. Again, there is
absolutely no sensory experience here which forces it to be considered an
innate idea. This is only one example from the non-human world. Surely there
are countless others one can look to as being apart from sensory experience.
Implications
This section will assume
the acceptance of innate ideas.
From the naturalistic
point of view it may be that innate ideas came about because of evolution.
Humans are more cognitively complex than almost any other animal known to
exist, and the theory of evolution states that all living beings have a common
ancestor. It could be the case that this ancestor evolved motivational innate
ideas, whereas practical innate ideas have evolved in a species-specific manner.
This in itself calls into question the very nature of ideas and of a mind. It
is undeniable that a brain scan will never reveal precisely what a person is
thinking about, or that ideas are something greater than a physical entity
somewhere in the brain. Innate ideas could be the stepping stone to discovering
something unheard of in regards to knowledge that I have no way of
understanding today. Science once believed the Earth to be the center of the
universe. We cannot rule out anything as a possibility, no matter how silly it
may seem to us now.
Continuing with Kant,
skepticism is heavily affected by their existence. Senses may be deceptive,
memory may fail, but pleasure and power are undeniable in the human psyche. The
ideas necessary to survival are things a being must know with no doubt to live.
No one may deny that they are skeptical that they think about power or pleasure
whenever they commit to an action. Every other belief or experience may come
into question but it is impossible to question these motivations. Even in
questioning every other belief, or even the beliefs themselves, the desire in
disproving these beliefs is either power or pleasure. There is no way to
disprove them without proving them in doing so.
Closing Remarks
I hope this conversation
has made the impact I intended. Empiricism is an important theory in explaining
how we come to know about the world around us and I endorse it as the only way
to gain practical knowledge of our world. However, there must be concessions
made to understanding why we seek knowledge instead of purely focusing on the
knowledge itself gained. Every idea we obtain from experience will be rooted in
the ideas we do not even understand why we have in the first place. Perhaps a
better philosopher than myself can explain why these innate ideas are so
prevalent, and perhaps they will prove me wrong in the
process. Either way, I consider the case I have laid out here for innate ideas
to provide powerful discussions to further the advances in understanding how we
think and why we think.
[1]
"EmpiricismAbout Our Definitions: All Forms of a Word (noun, Verb, Etc.)
Are Now Displayed on One Page." Http://www.merriam-webster.com.
Merriam-Webster, n.d. Web. 12 Nov. 2012.
<http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/empiricism>.
[2]
Chisholm, Roderick M. The Problem of the Criterion,. Milwaukee:
Marquette UP, 1973. Print.
[3]
Dorbulo, Jon. "Great Philosophers: Locke." Great Philosophers:
Hypatia. Oregon State University, 2002. Web. 12 Nov. 2012.
<http://oregonstate.edu/instruct/phl201/modules/Philosophers/Locke/locke.html>.
[4]
"John Locke." Http://www.iep.utm.edu/locke/. Ed. James Fieser
and Bradley Dowden. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 17 Apr. 2001. Web. 12
Nov. 2012. <http://www.iep.utm.edu/locke/>.
[5]
McCormick, Matt. "Immanuel Kant: Metaphysics." Http://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta.
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 17 Apr. 2001. Web. 12 Nov. 2012.
<http://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta>.
[6]
McCormick, Matt. "Immanuel Kant: Metaphysics." Http://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta.
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 17 Apr. 2001. Web. 12 Nov. 2012.
<http://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta>.
[7]
Palmer, Donald. "The 17th and 18th Centuries." Looking at
Philosophy: The Unbearable Heaviness of Philosophy Made Lighter. Mountain
View, CA: Mayfield Pub., 1994. 124-204. Print.
[8]
"idea." Collins English Dictionary - Complete & Unabridged
10th Edition. HarperCollins Publishers. 12 Nov. 2012. <Dictionary.com http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/idea>.
[9]
Locke, John, and Kenneth Winkler. An Essay concerning Human Understanding:
Abridged, with Introduction and Notes. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub.,
1996. Print.
[10]
Scheler, Max. "Max Scheler: The Being of the Person." Ed. Dermot
Moran and Timothy Mooney. The Phenomenology Reader. Vol. 1. New York: Routledge,
2002. 203-26. Print.
[11]
Scheler, Max. "Max Scheler: The Being of the Person." Ed. Dermot
Moran and Timothy Mooney. The Phenomenology Reader. Vol. 1. New York:
Routledge, 2002. 203-26. Print.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)